Richardson's theorem
In mathematics, Richardson's theorem establishes the undecidability of the equality of real numbers defined by expressions involving integers, π, and exponential and sine functions. It was proved in 1968 by the mathematician and computer scientist Daniel Richardson of the University of Bath.
Specifically, the class of expressions for which the theorem holds is that generated by rational numbers, the number π, the number ln 2, the variable x, the operations of addition, subtraction, multiplication, composition, and the sin, exp, and abs functions.
For some classes of expressions generated by other primitives than in Richardson's theorem, there exist algorithms that can determine whether an expression is zero.[1]
Statement of the theorem
[edit]Richardson's theorem can be stated as follows:[2] Let E be a set of expressions that represent functions. Suppose that E includes these expressions:
- x (representing the identity function)
- ex (representing the exponential functions)
- sin x (representing the sin function)
- all rational numbers, ln 2, and π (representing constant functions that ignore their input and produce the given number as output)
Suppose E is also closed under a few standard operations. Specifically, suppose that if A and B are in E, then all of the following are also in E:
- A + B (representing the pointwise addition of the functions that A and B represent)
- A − B (representing pointwise subtraction)
- AB (representing pointwise multiplication)
- A∘B (representing the composition of the functions represented by A and B)
Then the following decision problems are unsolvable:
- Deciding whether an expression A in E represents a function that is nonnegative everywhere
- If E includes also the expression |x| (representing the absolute value function), deciding whether an expression A in E represents a function that is zero everywhere
- If E includes an expression B representing a function whose antiderivative has no representative in E, deciding whether an expression A in E represents a function whose antiderivative can be represented in E. (Example: has an antiderivative in the elementary functions if and only if a = 0.)
Extensions
[edit]After Hilbert's tenth problem was solved in 1970, B. F. Caviness observed that the use of ex and ln 2 could be removed.[3] Wang later noted that under the same assumptions under which the question of whether there was x with A(x) < 0 was insolvable, the question of whether there was x with A(x) = 0 was also insolvable.[4]
Miklós Laczkovich removed also the need for π and reduced the use of composition.[5] In particular, given an expression A(x) in the ring generated by the integers, x, sin xn, and sin(x sin xn) (for n ranging over positive integers), both the question of whether A(x) > 0 for some x and whether A(x) = 0 for some x are unsolvable.
By contrast, the Tarski–Seidenberg theorem says that the first-order theory of the real field is decidable, so it is not possible to remove the sine function entirely.
See also
[edit]- Constant problem – Problem of deciding whether an expression equals zero
- Elementary function – Mathematical function
- Tarski's high school algebra problem – Mathematical problem
References
[edit]- ^ Dan Richardson and John Fitch, 1994, "The identity problem for elementary functions and constants Archived 2024-05-04 at the Wayback Machine", Proceedings of the international symposium on Symbolic and algebraic computation, pp. 85–290.
- ^ Richardson, Daniel (1968). "Some Undecidable Problems Involving Elementary Functions of a Real Variable". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 33 (4): 514–520. doi:10.2307/2271358. JSTOR 2271358. Zbl 0175.27404.
- ^ Caviness, B. F. (1970). "On Canonical Forms and Simplification". Journal of the ACM. 17 (2): 385–396. doi:10.1145/321574.321591.
- ^ Wang, P. S. (1974). "The undecidability of the existence of zeros of real elementary functions". Journal of the Association for Computing Machinery. 21 (4): 586–589. doi:10.1145/321850.321856.
- ^ Laczkovich, Miklós (2003). "The removal of π from some undecidable problems involving elementary functions". Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 131 (7): 2235–2240. doi:10.1090/S0002-9939-02-06753-9.
Further reading
[edit]- Petkovšek, Marko; Wilf, Herbert S.; Zeilberger, Doron (1996). A = B. A. K. Peters. p. 212. ISBN 1-56881-063-6. Archived from the original on 2006-01-29.